It is a tragedy that
this kind of political philosophy is so overlooked. Carol Gould is one of the few authors
out there who takes democracy seriously enough to construct a theory from it,
and yet her work is often missed when reviewing the literature. Despite the
fidelity of Gould's work to the democratic project she barely makes it into the
democracy entry on the Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy except as a
foot-note. In fact the theories of democracy that are touched on in the SEP are
largely restricted to liberal, neo-liberal and aristo-monarchic positions.
So why has the work of Gould and her peers been so ignored?
Personally I think the problem lies with its ambigious classification and heritage. The arguments that Gould offers are too radical to fit in with
the liberalism of Rawls and Dahl yet too reformist to be discussed alongside
Anarchism. Furthermore, theories of participatory democratic theory are so
multifaceted in terms of their origins that it is very difficult to slot them into one singular account of modern democratic theory, ergo
they are often left out.
Pragmatically speaking, this kind of book would be very
informative for those interested in anarchism: in so far as it delineates an actual modus operandi for
future "liberated territories". While Gould does retain both the
state and the market as methods of organisation they are so augmented by the
time she re-formulates them that they can barely be considered to be the kind
of things that anarchists rail against. Her view of a democratic economy, for
instance, largely mirrors anarcho-syndicalism (though it is never described in
such terms) and her approach to governance consists of bottom up participatory
structures. In short, the market that Gould wants is a socialist one and the territorial
governance that she envisions needs little tweaking to defy conventional
anarchist critiques.
It's not all one way traffic though. Gould's model of
democracy could learn a few things from anarchism vis-a-vis institutional
practises. Her vision of democratic participation, the actual
making of decisions, seems to be focused on conversations followed by, what one
would assume to be, a majority vote. Her theory's defence against majoritarian
tyranny and persistent minorities is simply an appeal to the democratic
character of its subjects. The
anarchist tradition could offer here both a model of consensus decision
making and an emphasis on decentralisation in order to build a more robust systemic response to the various upsets that can result from
majority rule.
The social ontology and the ethical underpinnings of her
theory remind me of Susan Neiman's "Why Grow Up?": at its core
there's a really invigorating vision of humans as creative beings seeking
self-betterment. In line with this, the book's content rests on a moral conception of
self-determination as a requirement for human self-development. Gould rejects
both liberal individualism and socialistic holism for an intermediate ontology
that views humans as individuals whose identities are understood, pursued and realised
through social relationships.
In terms of economic justice, this social ontology provides her with a twin pronged attack. If the purpose of freedom is self-development then this defends both "welfarism" and worker control of the means of production. "Welfarism" is justified on the grounds that everyone is entitled, where possible, to the resources that make self-development possible and the "rights to worker control" become justified where work is a social activity in which self-development takes place.
In terms of economic justice, this social ontology provides her with a twin pronged attack. If the purpose of freedom is self-development then this defends both "welfarism" and worker control of the means of production. "Welfarism" is justified on the grounds that everyone is entitled, where possible, to the resources that make self-development possible and the "rights to worker control" become justified where work is a social activity in which self-development takes place.
The book is strikingly comprehensive. "Rethinking Democracy" deals with topics as varied and concrete as the
relationship between freedom and equality; the role of technical expertise in
participatory democracy, and the
consequences Gould's theory has for debates surrounding global interventionism.
If you want an idea of how anarchist principles might play out in a future
society, but can't stand the more tendentious elements of anarchist rhetoric,
then this is a worthwhile read.